Every individual is continually exerting himself to find out the most
advantageous employment for whatever capital he can command. It is his
own advantage, indeed, and not that of the society, which he has in
view. But the study of his own advantage naturally, or rather
necessarily, leads him to prefer that employment which is most
advantageous to the society.
The greatest improvement in the productive powers of
labor, and the greater part of the skill, dexterity, and judgment with
which it is anywhere directed, or applied, seem to have been the
effects of the division of labor....
To take an example, therefore, the
trade of the pin-maker; a workman not educated to this business, nor
acquainted with the use of the machinery employed in it, could scarce,
perhaps, with his utmost industry, make one pin in a day, and
certainly could not make twenty. But in the way in which this business
is now carried on, not only the whole work is a peculiar trade, but it
is divided into a number of branches, of which the greater part are
likewise peculiar trades. One man draws out the wire, another
straights it, a third cuts it, a fourth points it, a fifth grinds it
at the top for receiving, the head; to make the head requires two or
three distinct operations; to put it on is a peculiar business, to
whiten the pins is another; it is even a trade by itself to put them
into the paper; and the important business of making a pin is, in this
manner, divided into about eighteen distinct operations, which, in
some factories, are all performed by distinct hands, though in others
the same man will sometimes perform two or three of them. Each
person, therefore, making a tenth part of forty-eight thousand pins,
might be considered as making four thousand eight hundred pins in a
day. But if they had all wrought separately and independently, and
without any of them having been educated to this peculiar business,
they certainly could not each of them have made twenty, perhaps not
one pin in a day.
This division of labor, from which so
many advantages are derived, is not originally the effect of any human
wisdom, which foresees and intends that universal opulence to which it
gives occasion. It is the necessary, though very slow and gradual
consequence of a certain propensity in human nature which has in view
no such extensive utility; the propensity to truck, barter, and
exchange one thing for another.....
It is the great multiplication of the productions of all the
different arts, in consequence of the division of labor, which
occasions, in a well-governed society, that universal opulence
which extends itself to the lowest ranks of the people. Every workman
has a great quantity of his own work to dispose of beyond what he
himself has occasion for; and every other workman being exactly in the
same situation, he is enabled to exchange a great quantity of his own
goods for a great quantity, or, what comes to the same thing, for the
price of a great quantity of theirs. He supplies them abundantly with
what they have occasion for, and they accommodate him as amply with
what he has occasion for, and a general plenty diffuses itself through
all the different ranks of the society....
And it is by treaty, by barter, and by purchase that we obtain from
one another the greater part of those mutual good offices which we
stand in need of, so it is this same trucking disposition which
originally gives occasion to the division of labor. In a tribe of
hunters or shepherds a particular person makes bows and arrows, for
example, with more readiness and dexterity than any other. He
frequently exchanges them for cattle or for venison with his
companions; and he finds at last that he can in this manner get more
cattle and venison than if he himself went to the field to catch them.
From a regard to his own interest, therefore, the making of bows and
arrows grows to be his chief business, and he becomes a sort of armorer, etc......
When the division of labor has been once thoroughly established, it is
but a very small part of a man's wants which the produce of his own
labor can supply. He supplies the far greater part of them by
exchanging that surplus part of the produce of his own labor, which is
over and above his own consumption, for such parts of the produce of
other men's labor as he has occasion for. Every man thus lives by
exchanging, or becomes in some measure a merchant, and the society
itself grows to be what is properly a commercial society.
Man has almost constant occasion
for the help of his brethren, and it is in vain for him to expect it
from their benevolence only. He will be more likely to prevail if he
can interest their self-love in his favor, and show them that it is
for their own advantage to do for him what he requires of them.
Whoever offers to another a bargain of any kind, proposes to do this.
Give me that which I want, and you shall have this which you want, is
the meaning of every such offer; and it is in this manner that we
obtain from one another the far greater art of those good offices
which we stand in need of. It is not from the benevolence of the
butcher, the brewer, or the baker that we expect our dinner, but
from their regard to their own interest.
When the division of labor first began to take place, this
power of exchanging must frequently have been very much clogged and
embarrassed in its operations. One man, we shall suppose, has more of
a certain commodity than he himself has occasion for, while another
has less. The former consequently would be glad to dispose of, and the
latter to purchase, a part of this superfluity. But if this latter
should chance to have nothing that the former stands in need of, no
exchange can be made between them. The butcher has more meat in his
shop than he himself can consume, and the brewer and the baker would
each of them be willing to purchase a part of it. But they have
nothing to offer in exchange, except the different productions of
their respective trades, and the butcher is already provided with all
the bread and beer which he has immediate occasion for. No exchange
can, in this case, be made between them. In order to avoid the
inconvenience of such situations, every prudent man in every period of
society, after the first establishment of the division of labor, must
naturally have endeavored to manage his affairs in such a manner as to
have at all times by him, besides the peculiar produce of his own
industry, a certain quantity of some one commodity or other, such as
he imagined few people would be likely to refuse in exchange for their
produce....It is in this manner that money has become in all civilized
nations the universal instrument of commerce, by the intervention of
which goods of all kinds are bought and sold, or exchanged for one
another....
The actual price at which any commodity is commonly sold is
called its market price. It may either be above, or below, or
exactly the same with its natural price. The market price of every
particular commodity is regulated by the proportion between the
quantity which is actually brought to market, and the demand of
those who are willing to pay the natural price of the commodity, or
the whole value of the rent, labor, and profit, which must be paid
in order to bring it thither.
When the quantity of any commodity which is brought to market falls
short of the effectual demand, a competition will
immediately begin among the buyers, and the market price will rise to the natural price, according as either the greatness of the
deficiency, or the wealth and wanton luxury of the competitors, happen
to animate more or less the eagerness of the competition.
When the quantity brought to market exceeds the effectual demand,
it cannot be all sold to those who are willing to pay the whole value
of the rent, wages, and profit, which must be paid in order to bring
it thither, and the market price will sink to more or less the
natural price, according as the greatness of the excess increases more
or less the competition of the sellers, or according as it happens to
be more or less important to them to get immediately rid of the
commodity.
When the quantity brought to market is just sufficient to
supply the effectual demand, and no more, the market price naturally
comes to be either exactly, or as nearly as can be judged of, the same
with the natural price. The whole quantity upon hand can be disposed
of for this price, and cannot be disposed of for more. The competition
of the different dealers obliges them all to accept of this price, but
does not oblige them to accept of less.
Such fluctuations affect both the value and the rate either of
wages or of profit, according as the market happens to be either
overstocked or understocked with commodities or with labor; with work
done, or with work to be done. But though the market price of every
particular commodity is in this manner continually gravitating to the natural price.
When by an increase in the effectual demand, the market price of
some particular commodity happens to rise a good deal above the
natural price, those who employ their stocks in supplying that market
are generally gifted with great profit. However, this profit would tempt so many new rivals to employ
their stocks in the same way that the effectual demand being fully
supplied, the market price would soon be reduced to the natural price.
The annual revenue of every society is always precisely equal to the
exchangeable value of the whole annual produce of its industry, or
rather is precisely the same thing with that exchangeable value. As
every individual, therefore endeavours as much as he can both to employ
his capital in the support of domestic industry, and so to direct that
industry that its produce may be of the greatest value; every individual
necessarily labours to render the annual revenue of the society as great
as he can. He generally, indeed, neither, intends to promote the public
interest, nor knows how much he is promoting it.
By preferring the
support of domestic to that of foreign industry, he intends only his own
security, and by directing that industry in such a manner as its produce
may be of the greatest value, he intends only his own gain, and he is in
this, as in many other cases, led by an invisible hand to promote an end
which was no part of his intention. Nor is it always the worse for the
society that it was no part of it. By pursuing his own interest he
frequently promotes that of the society more effectually than when he
really intends to promote it. I have never known much good done by those
who affected to trade for the public good. It is an affectation, indeed,
not very common among merchants, and very few words need be employed in
dissuading them from it.
Source:
From: Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the
Wealth of Nations, 2 Vols., Everyman's Library (London: Dent &
Sons, 1904), Vol. I, passim.
Scanned and organized by Jerome S. Arkenberg, Cal. State Fullerton.
The text has been modernized by Prof. Arkenberg.
This text is part of the
Internet
Modern History Sourcebook. The Sourcebook is a collection of
public domain and copy-permitted texts for introductory level classes
in modern European and World history.
Unless otherwise indicated the specific electronic
form of the document is copyright. Permission is granted for
electronic copying, distribution in print form for educational
purposes and personal use. If you do reduplicate the document,
indicate the source. No permission is granted for commercial use of
the Sourcebook.
Paul Halsall, January 1999
halsall@fordham.edu
|